First Page
1337
Abstract
In Tort Law in America: An Intellectual History, I made the general argument that the development of tort law in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries had been more influenced by ideas than previous scholars had suggested.' In making that argument I employed the terms "ideas" and "influence" at multiple levels of generality. The argument would perhaps have been better under- stood if I had more clearly particularized the specificity and generality of my claims about ideas as causal agents.
At the most specific level, I employed the term "ideas" to refer to particular doctrinal and policy proposals for tort law advanced by particular scholars and judges. Examples would be the "vice principar' doctrine, or the doctrine of "last clear chance," or proposals for a system of workmen's compensation governing certain types of industrial accidents. On a more general level, I used the term "ideas" to describe the starting presuppositions about the purposes and goals of the American tort system that drove those proposals, such as the idea that the primary purpose of tort law should be to compensate injured persons, or the competing idea that its primary purpose should be to deter or to punish risky conduct.
At a still higher level of abstraction, I used the term "ideas" to refer to broad conceptions of law, as embodied in competing jurisprudential "schools" that surfaced in the American legal profession in the late nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Examples of those "schools" include what I called "conceptualism," which treated law as the embodiment of universal principles of civil conduct represented in the concepts that were embedded in legal doctrines; "realism," which equated law with the current doctrines and policies that courts believed had the greatest functional efficacy; and "neoconceptualism," which revived an image of law, including tort law, as ordered by comprehensive principles, the source of which was no longer immanent universal truths but general insights about human behavior drawn from other scholarly disciplines.
Finally, I used the term "ideas" to refer to changing perceptions of the sources of human knowledge in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, a span of time in which human-oriented models for explaining and controlling change in the natural and social worlds, centering on forms of scientific inquiry, replaced externally- oriented models, centered on religious, natural, or historical forces.
My different uses of the term "ideas" were not accompanied by an explicit theory of the causal relationships among the sets of ideas I described. Instead I drew the general conclusion that all of those sets of ideas "influenced" the course of tort law in nineteenth- and twentieth-century America. I continue to agree with that conclusion, but in this Essay, which surveys developments in tort law in the last two decades of the twentieth century, I want to particularize what I mean by ideas and their influence.
Recommended Citation
G. Edward White,
The Unexpected Persistence of Negligence, 1980-2000,
54 Vanderbilt Law Review
1337
(2001)
Available at: https://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/vlr/vol54/iss3/21